Mere Featherless Bipeds
This article by Carlin Romano raises a lot of very interesting issues. I don’t know nearly enough (by which I mean I know nothing at all) about the subject to judge how fair or accurate any of it is – but the issues raised are interesting in any case, and I propose to mumble over them, so there.
The desire to portray great thinkers as disembodied argument machines remains a powerful force in analytic philosophy. Think of it as a slice of amour-propre, part of the arrogant wish to be seen as timelessly, noncontingently right about everything. It can move acolytes to depict thinker-heroes as dynamos of pure intellect rather than peers: mere featherless bipeds whose thoughts bear clear markings from their beliefs, fears, and weaknesses.
See, that’s an interesting idea whether it’s true or not. The idea of people wanting to be seen as timelessly, noncontingently right about everything – there’s something fascinating about that (as well as very funny, of course). I suppose I’m interested in various forms of déformation professionelle, and especially in academic ones, so the thought of a special need or desire to be a disembodied argument machine makes me sit up and take notice.
It also interests me because it seems to me not altogether mistaken to want to separate the thoughts from the biography. I can think of other reasons philosophers (among other people) would want to do that that aren’t mere vanity – so Romano’s article partly goes against the grain of my thinking, which is to say it challenges some of my assumptions. I don’t always like having my assumptions challenged – when the students at Patrick Henry college (no, I’m not going to stop mentioning that place any time soon, why do you ask?) babble about the joys of subordinating women I don’t find it particularly interesting or thought-provoking – but sometimes I do.
It seems reasonable to want to try to do that, at least, for reasons to do with clarity. As part of an effort to strip away extraneous details in order to get at the thoughts as – in themselves they really are. That may be an absurd, hopeless, impossible, even risky wish, but still I can see why people would want to try – at least I think I can. But the idea that it’s pretty much just presentation of self is…interesting.
I keep thinking of Lydgate. In Middlemarch, you know. Eliot does a brilliant job on him: he’s the classic case of a would-be impersonal, dedicated, above it all scientist who in fact is riddled with unaware vanity.
Like many of his colleagues, Hart largely avoided anecdotes, biography, and detailed sociological evidence because it didn’t fit with proper Oxford philosophical method. Clear, precise, and commonsensical, he kept his personal life out of his books. Lacey’s study consequently hit the jurisprudence community like a Kitty Kelley exposé implanted in a Festschrift.
Not all bad, the keeping the personal life out business. One can get weary of the anecdotes about evenings wandering around Jakarta or Rangoon. I’m just saying.
But Lacey’s achievement triggered an attack on her this year by New York University philosophy professor Thomas Nagel, author of – unsurprisingly – The View From Nowhere. Complained Nagel in the London Review of Books, “I felt that I was learning too much that was none of my business…Nagel also maintains that despite Lacey’s distinguished academic position, she is “not equipped … to deal with the philosophical background. When she talks about the ‘paradox of analysis’ or about the differences between J.L. Austin and Wittgenstein, she is lost.” Upping the insult quotient, Nagel maintains that Lacey “seems to have a weak grasp of what philosophy is,” a claim he repeats several times. False in every respect. Lacey, far more industriously than Nagel, backs her statements throughout.
Now, that interests me because I happen to have read just a couple of days ago a letter from Simon Blackburn and Jeremy Waldron to the LRB protesting exactly the same thing.
We were puzzled and depressed to read Thomas Nagel’s patronising review of Nicola Lacey’s biography of Herbert Hart. In particular, his sweeping claim that the author is ‘lost’ when it comes to philosophical issues is both ungenerous and unsupported.
So the context and explanation Romano gives seems to make sense of something puzzling.
Indeed, Lacey utterly foresees Nagel’s line of insult. She specifically anticipates his assertion that Wittgenstein thought understanding “has to be pursued primarily by reasoning rather than by empirical observation,” noting “Wittgenstein’s emphasis on the embeddedness of language games within social practices.” In her view, Hart, like Nagel, never adopted an approach to reality as reportorial as Wittgenstein’s because it “undermines the pretensions of philosophy as the ‘master discipline’ which illuminates our access to knowledge about the world.”
Now that really interests me, because it’s something I’ve heard before, from people I know who have a somewhat disrespectful view of philosophy – who say it likes to see itself as ‘the queen of the sciences’ and that that self-vision can make philosophers a tad grandiose. I have no idea, myself. I don’t know any philosophers. I live in a tiny fishing village on the edge of an ice shelf in the far far north, and philosophers don’t get up here much. But I have heard people (who do know some philosophers) say so. Thus it’s interesting.
The sad upshot of this latest sighting of the disembodied thinker is that a champion of “philosophy” thinks truth matters less than keeping up appearances.
Ouch.
Some comments on this article have already been made. I will repost all of them here.
OB are you going to comment on that assinine article about H.L. Hart and Lacey that was recently posted in the news section?
One amongst many bones to pick with it is that it implies that ALL analytic philosophy is ahistorical. However, it is continental textual criticism that is often ahistorical. Roland Barthes “Death of the Author” comes to mind. Derrida thinks that not only the author has died but the reader too. Talk about ahistorical approaches to biography and texts, sheesh. Just read Derrida’s essay “Otobiography” from the collection “The Ear of the Other.”
| ChrisJ | 2005-06-30 – 19:10:01 |
I’m confused by what you find objectionable, ChrisJ. The article doesn’t declare or imply that all analytic philosophy is ahistorical: The emphasis is clearly and always on analytic philosophers’ pretentions to being a-personal – conducted through pure reason by pure reasoners, not conducted by people with beliefs and personalities and agendas. Nagel serves as a clear illustration, as do all the philosophers who whined and carried on over any hint that Wittgenstein ever had a personal life or a psychology. Are all analytic philosophers committed to such delusions? Of course not. But it is certainly a common sort of attitude amongst them – and I’ve seen plenty of evidence of that myself.
| G | 2005-06-30 – 19:44:46 |
Here is a quote from the article.
“Lacey simply doesn’t share Nagel’s typical analyst view that AHISTORICAL, nonsociological, fact-free reasoning is the end-all and be-all of philosophy. While expressing great respect and affection for Hart, she indicates early on that her feminist and Foucauldian appreciation of power’s role in shaping institutions makes her more critical of Hart and his facts-lite analytic jurisprudence than she once was.”
This constant reference to “facts free” or “facts-lite” is irritating as well. We have seen devastating critiques of Foucault on this site before, so i won’t comment on that. This sort of stereotyping is what perpetuates the so-called analytic vs continental debate and I for one am tired of it. You can’t give one example (Nagel) in this case and infer that his style of philosophy is “typical.” This is a hasty generalization.
I don’t even need the word ahistorical for my point. You may replace it with a-personal in my original post and the point still holds.
| ChrisJ | 2005-06-30 – 21:31:53 |
Well, you pin-pointed the use of the word, but I still think you misapprehend the sentiment. The target here is the all-too-common notion among analytic philosophers that REASONING ALONE – somehow carried out independently by these fascinating mythical pure reasoners without histories, social contexts, etc. – is what philosophy properly is and does. Is this view universal? No. Is it fairly typical? In my long experience as a student and teacher of philosophy, yes.
To use specific examples to illustrate a general claim is not a hasty generalization, because the general claim isn’t being deduced from the examples as if they were data points. The general claim is supported on other grounds – in this case, the tendency of analytic philosophers to react (rather, to over-react) to biographies of their intellectual heroes as if they were somehow pernicious and underhanded assaults on philosophy itself. The general claim about many philosophers’ attachment to this non-contextual model of philosophy (philosophy without actual philosophers) explains this recurring reaction to biography pretty well, seems to me.
That said, I agree with your irritation at the “fact-free” aspect of the article. That might be a valid criticism of Wittgenstein, which is where it was (sneakily) introduced, but there is no support for generalization of it to analytic philosophy – nor even for its application to Nagel. Various kinds of naturalism, for just one very large category of examples, are very respectable and influential fact-focused philosophical inquiries. In contrast, a profound aversion to facts, both concretely and conceptually, is a hallmark of continental philosophy of recent vintage.
| G | 2005-06-30 – 22:57:57 |
The claim that it is “typical” or “all too common” that analytical philosophers rely on “reasoning alone” remains unsupported other than by anecdote.
| ChrisJ | 2005-07-01 – 01:54:37 |
OB, I hit your link to the article and read it, and copied that final quotation, before reading your comment.
“The sad upshot of this latest sighting of the disembodied thinker is that a champion of “philosophy” thinks truth matters less than keeping up appearances.”
Thomas Nagel has made important contributions in analytical philosophy, and half an hour’s googling will provide ample evidence of this, so the scare quotes are just snarky. Equally, anybody remotely familiar with his work (and I have read only a little) would see that he has considered the concept of truth far more deeply than most literary critics, so this point displays cavalier ignorance. Who the hell is Carlin Romano, anyway?
I respect Thomas Nagel as much as anyone. His short paper “What is it like to be a bat?” is one of the most interesting and influential philosophy of mind essays ever, and I’ve re-read it a few times more out of sheer appreciation than for any particular scholarly purpose. But the quote in question is aimed quite specifically at Nagel’s unjustified attack on and dismissal of Hart’s biographer. Nagel’s review was so full of cheap shots that it even inspired a public upbraid from Simon Blackburn and Jeremy Waldron (which OB also linked to): It’s worth scrolling down from Blackburn and Waldron’s letter to Nagel’s defensive response – which, frankly, does not inspire much confidence in the objectivity he so prizes.
Ditto. I find Nagel generally illuminating, and ‘What is it like to be a bat?’ is one of the immortals. But that doesn’t mean he couldn’t have been wrong about the Lacey book, or that there is nothing interesting to say about the possible sources of his wrongness.
And Romano isn’t a lit crit, by the way, he’s a philosopher himself, and he writes excellent articles for the Chronicle and the Philadelphia Inquirer – there are many links to them at B&W.
There we go again.. Nagels ‘defensive’ response. What kind of response would you expect?
It is an interesting exchange.